登陆注册
15397500000026

第26章

In estimating what is good or evil in itself, as distinguished from what can be so called only relatively, the following points are to be considered.Either a rational principle is already conceived, as of itself the determining principle of the will, without regard to possible objects of desire (and therefore by the more legislative form of the maxim), and in that case that principle is a practical a priori law, and pure reason is supposed to be practical of itself.The law in that case determines the will directly; the action conformed to it is good in itself; a will whose maxim always conforms to this law is good absolutely in every respect and is the supreme condition of all good.Or the maxim of the will is consequent on a determining principle of desire which presupposes an object of pleasure or pain, something therefore that pleases or displeases, and the maxim of reason that we should pursue the former and avoid the latter determines our actions as good relatively to our inclination, that is, good indirectly, i.e., relatively to a different end to which they are means), and in that case these maxims can never be called laws, but may be called rational practical precepts.The end itself, the pleasure that we seek, is in the latter case not a good but a welfare;not a concept of reason, but an empirical concept of an object of sensation; but the use of the means thereto, that is, the action, is nevertheless called good (because rational deliberation is required for it), not however, good absolutely, but only relatively to our sensuous nature, with regard to its feelings of pleasure and displeasure; but the will whose maxim is affected thereby is not a pure will; this is directed only to that in which pure reason by itself can be practical.

This is the proper place to explain the paradox of method in a critique of practical reason, namely, that the concept of good and evil must not be determined before the moral law (of which it seems as if it must be the foundation), but only after it and by means of it.

In fact, even if we did not know that the principle of morality is a pure a priori law determining the will, yet, that we may not assume principles quite gratuitously, we must, at least at first, leave it undecided, whether the will has merely empirical principles of determination, or whether it has not also pure a priori principles;for it is contrary to all rules of philosophical method to assume as decided that which is the very point in question.Supposing that we wished to begin with the concept of good, in order to deduce from it the laws of the will, then this concept of an object (as a good) would at the same time assign to us this object as the sole determining principle of the will.Now, since this concept had not any practical a priori law for its standard, the criterion of good or evil could not be placed in anything but the agreement of the object with our feeling of pleasure or pain; and the use of reason could only consist in determining in the first place this pleasure or pain in connexion with all the sensations of my existence, and in the second place the means of securing to myself the object of the pleasure.Now, as experience alone can decide what conforms to the feeling of pleasure, and by hypothesis the practical law is to be based on this as a condition, it follows that the possibility of a priori practical laws would be at once excluded, because it was imagined to be necessary first of all to find an object the concept of which, as a good, should constitute the universal though empirical principle of determination of the will.But what it was necessary to inquire first of all was whether there is not an a priori determining principle of the will (and this could never be found anywhere but in a pure practical law, in so far as this law prescribes to maxims merely their form without regard to an object).Since, however, we laid the foundation of all practical law in an object determined by our conceptions of good and evil, whereas without a previous law that object could not be conceived by empirical concepts, we have deprived ourselves beforehand of the possibility of even conceiving a pure practical law.On the other hand, if we had first investigated the latter analytically, we should have found that it is not the concept of good as an object that determines the moral law and makes it possible, but that, on the contrary, it is the moral law that first determines the concept of good and makes it possible, so far as it deserves the name of good absolutely.

同类推荐
  • 荣枯鉴

    荣枯鉴

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 地藏菩萨仪轨

    地藏菩萨仪轨

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 灌畦暇语

    灌畦暇语

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 御制救度佛母赞

    御制救度佛母赞

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
  • 乙巳占

    乙巳占

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。
热门推荐
  • 终极蝴蝶

    终极蝴蝶

    故事总在最深处.讲述一个传奇的推理故事,其中讲述一个似神非神的旅途故事,到底是真实可以解释,还是玄幻,待破解、
  • 壁炉山庄的安妮

    壁炉山庄的安妮

    安妮已经是有着六个孩子的母亲了。在这个家庭里,每个人都有些有趣的小故事,尤其是性格迥异的孩子们的童年趣事,如同珍珠一样串起来,让这本书显得温馨美满。
  • 九剑封仙

    九剑封仙

    那一年,指尖划过的是你那如雪的肌肤,那一年,眼中看见的是你那消散的身躯。坠入红尘,承受生死轮回之苦,只为寻找你的身影。
  • 我说你听

    我说你听

    管弦齐奏,共鸣青春。怀旧经典,忆昔思今!这是一部平凡的作品,记录了一代人的成长轨迹。90后为何成为话题不断、被刻板印象化的一代?TA们究竟是我们想象的那个样子吗?他们曾向世界庄严宣告:90后有着苏轼的豪放,也有李清照的婉约,更有独一无二的我们自己!我的青春谁做主?奋斗吧!骚年!
  • 逆路血战

    逆路血战

    血犹热,战八方,守土开疆披戎装。看九州,烽轻扬,君道莫笑醉沙场。诛戎狄,酒一觞,凯旋踏歌复三年。当为自由而争的突击者遇到为信仰而战的保卫者。当冰与火再次碰撞,两者逐鹿中原,究竟谁胜谁负?狭路相逢,勇者相争。看小小兵痞如何翻转战场,带领战友呼啸山河。
  • 福妻驾到

    福妻驾到

    现代饭店彪悍老板娘魂穿古代。不分是非的极品婆婆?三年未归生死不明的丈夫?心狠手辣的阴毒亲戚?贪婪而好色的地主老财?吃上顿没下顿的贫困宭境?不怕不怕,神仙相助,一技在手,天下我有!且看现代张悦娘,如何身带福气玩转古代,开面馆、收小弟、左纳财富,右傍美男,共绘幸福生活大好蓝图!!!!快本新书《天媒地聘》已经上架开始销售,只要3.99元即可将整本书抱回家,你还等什么哪,赶紧点击下面的直通车,享受乐乐精心为您准备的美食盛宴吧!)
  • 玄幻情缘:别说爱我

    玄幻情缘:别说爱我

    玄幻世界,和爱的人一起闯荡,是什么体验?本书告诉你。和不爱的人一起闯荡,是什么体验?本书也会告诉你。
  • 有你们的日子春风十里

    有你们的日子春风十里

    青涩的初恋能否白头偕老欢歌笑语的同伴能否永远陪伴......
  • 当精灵爱上凡人之穿越到古代

    当精灵爱上凡人之穿越到古代

    本书主角从精灵变成人类,又因为一款后宫游戏穿越到了古代?!敬请期待……
  • 机器猫的口袋

    机器猫的口袋

    一群高智商的人利用善与恶的公式杀人救人…